天下书楼
会员中心 我的书架

CHAPTER IV. THE LAMP OF BEAUTY.

(快捷键←)[上一章]  [回目录]  [下一章](快捷键→)

i. it was stated, in the outset of the preceding chapter, that the value of architecture depended on two distinct characters: the one, the impression it receives from human power; the other, the image it bears of the natural creation. i have endeavored to show in what manner its majesty was attributable to a sympathy with the effort and trouble of human life (a sympathy as distinctly perceived in the gloom and mystery of form, as it is in the melancholy tones of sounds). i desire now to trace that happier element of its excellence, consisting in a noble rendering of images of beauty, derived chiefly from the external appearances of organic nature.

it is irrelevant to our present purpose to enter into any inquiry respecting the essential causes of impressions of beauty. i have partly expressed my thoughts on this matter in a previous work, and i hope to develope them hereafter. but since all such inquiries can only be founded on the ordinary understanding of what is meant by the term beauty, and since they presume that the feeling of mankind on this subject is universal and instinctive, i shall base my present investigation on this assumption; and only asserting that to be beautiful which i believe will be granted me to be so without dispute, i would endeavor shortly to trace the manner in which this element of delight is to be best engrafted upon architectural design, what are the purest sources from which it is to be derived, and what the errors to be avoided in its pursuit.

ii. it will be thought that i have somewhat rashly limited the elements of architectural beauty to imitative forms. i do not mean to assert that every arrangement of line is directly suggested by a natural object; but that all beautiful lines are adaptations of those which are commonest in the external creation; that in proportion to the richness of their association, the resemblance to natural work, as a type and help, must be more closely attempted, and more clearly seen; and that be[pg 101]yond a certain point, and that a very low one, man cannot advance in the invention of beauty, without directly imitating natural form. thus, in the doric temple, the triglyph and cornice are unimitative; or imitative only of artificial cuttings of wood. no one would call these members beautiful. their influence over us is in their severity and simplicity. the fluting of the column, which i doubt not was the greek symbol of the bark of the tree, was imitative in its origin, and feebly resembled many caniculated organic structures. beauty is instantly felt in it, but of a low order. the decoration proper was sought in the true forms of organic life, and those chiefly human. again: the doric capital was unimitative; but all the beauty it had was dependent on the precision of its ovolo, a natural curve of the most frequent occurrence. the ionic capital (to my mind, as an architectural invention, exceedingly base) nevertheless depended for all the beauty that it had on its adoption of a spiral line, perhaps the commonest of all that characterise the inferior orders of animal organism and habitation. farther progress could not be made without a direct imitation of the acanthus leaf.

again: the romanesque arch is beautiful as an abstract line. its type is always before us in that of the apparent vault of heaven, and horizon of the earth. the cylindrical pillar is always beautiful, for god has so moulded the stem of every tree that it is pleasant to the eyes. the pointed arch is beautiful; it is the termination of every leaf that shakes in summer wind, and its most fortunate associations are directly borrowed from the trefoiled grass of the field, or from the stars of its flowers. further than this, man's invention could not reach without frank imitation. his next step was to gather the flowers themselves, and wreathe them in his capitals.

iii. now, i would insist especially on the fact, of which i doubt not that further illustrations will occur to the mind of every reader, that all most lovely forms and thoughts are directly taken from natural objects; because i would fain be allowed to assume also the converse of this, namely, that forms which are not taken from natural objects must be ugly.[pg 102] i know this is a bold assumption; but as i have not space to reason out the points wherein essential beauty of form consists, that being far too serious a work to be undertaken in a bye way, i have no other resource than to use this accidental mark or test of beauty, of whose truth the considerations which i hope hereafter to lay before the reader may assure him. i say an accidental mark, since forms are not beautiful because they are copied from nature; only it is out of the power of man to conceive beauty without her aid. i believe the reader will grant me this, even from the examples above advanced; the degree of confidence with which it is granted must attach also to his acceptance of the conclusions which will follow from it; but if it be granted frankly, it will enable me to determine a matter of very essential importance, namely, what is or is not ornament. for there are many forms of so-called decoration in architecture, habitual, and received, therefore, with approval, or at all events without any venture at expression or dislike, which i have no hesitation in asserting to be not ornament at all, but to be ugly things, the expense of which ought in truth to be set down in the architect's contract, as "for monstrification." i believe that we regard these customary deformities with a savage complacency, as an indian does his flesh patterns and paint (all nations being in certain degrees and senses savage). i believe that i can prove them to be monstrous, and i hope hereafter to do so conclusively; but, meantime, i can allege in defence of my persuasion nothing but this fact of their being unnatural, to which the reader must attach such weight as he thinks it deserves. there is, however, a peculiar difficulty in using this proof; it requires the writer to assume, very impertinently, that nothing is natural but what he has seen or supposes to exist. i would not do this; for i suppose there is no conceivable form or grouping of forms but in some part of the universe an example of it may be found. but i think i am justified in considering those forms to be most natural which are most frequent; or, rather, that on the shapes which in the every-day world are familiar to the eyes of men, god has stamped those characters of beauty which he has made[pg 103] it man's nature to love; while in certain exceptional forms he has shown that the adoption of the others was not a matter of necessity, but part of the adjusted harmony of creation. i believe that thus we may reason from frequency to beauty and vice versa; that knowing a thing to be frequent, we may assume it to be beautiful; and assume that which is most frequent to be most beautiful: i mean, of course, visibly frequent; for the forms of things which are hidden in caverns of the earth, or in the anatomy of animal frames, are evidently not intended by their maker to bear the habitual gaze of man. and, again, by frequency i mean that limited and isolated frequency which is characteristic of all perfection; not mere multitude: as a rose is a common flower, but yet there are not so many roses on the tree as there are leaves. in this respect nature is sparing of her highest, and lavish of her less, beauty; but i call the flower as frequent as the leaf, because, each in its allotted quantity, where the one is, there will ordinarily be the other.

iv. the first so-called ornament, then, which i would attack is that greek fret, now, i believe, usually known by the italian name guilloche, which is exactly a case in point. it so happens that in crystals of bismuth formed by the unagitated cooling of the melted metal, there occurs a natural resemblance of it almost perfect. but crystals of bismuth not only are of unusual occurrence in every-day life, but their form is, as far as i know, unique among minerals; and not only unique, but only attainable by an artificial process, the metal itself never being found pure. i do not remember any other substance or arrangement which presents a resemblance to this greek ornament; and i think that i may trust my remembrance as including most of the arrangements which occur in the outward forms of common and familiar things. on this ground, then, i allege that ornament to be ugly; or, in the literal sense of the word, monstrous; different from anything which it is the nature of man to admire: and i think an uncarved fillet or plinth infinitely preferable to one covered with this vile concatenation of straight lines: unless indeed it be employed as a foil to a true ornament, which it[pg 104] may, perhaps, sometimes with advantage; or excessively small, as it occurs on coins, the harshness of its arrangement being less perceived.

v. often in association with this horrible design we find, in greek works, one which is as beautiful as this is painful—that egg and dart moulding, whose perfection in its place and way, has never been surpassed. and why is this? simply because the form of which it is chiefly composed is one not only familiar to us in the soft housing of the bird's nest, but happens to be that of nearly every pebble that rolls and murmurs under the surf of the sea, on all its endless shore. and with that a peculiar accuracy; for the mass which bears the light in this moulding is not in good greek work, as in the frieze of the erechtheum, merely of the shape of an egg. it is flattened on the upper surface, with a delicacy and keen sense of variety in the curve which it is impossible too highly to praise, attaining exactly that flattened, imperfect oval, which, in nine cases out of ten, will be the form of the pebble lifted at random from the rolled beach. leave out this flatness, and the moulding is vulgar instantly. it is singular also that the insertion of this rounded form in the hollow recess has a painted type in the plumage of the argus pheasant, the eyes of whose feathers are so shaded as exactly to represent an oval form placed in a hollow.

vi. it will evidently follow, upon our application of this test of natural resemblance, that we shall at once conclude that all perfectly beautiful forms must be composed of curves; since there is hardly any common natural form in which it is possible to discover a straight line. nevertheless, architecture, having necessarily to deal with straight lines essential to its purposes in many instances and to the expression of its power in others, must frequently be content with that measure of beauty which is consistent with such primal forms; and we may presume that utmost measure of beauty to have been attained when the arrangements of such lines are consistent with the most frequent natural groupings of them we can discover, although, to find right lines in nature at all, we may be compelled to do violence to her finished work, break[pg 105] through the sculptured and colored surfaces of her crags, and examine the processes of their crystallisation.

vii. i have just convicted the greek fret of ugliness, because it has no precedent to allege for its arrangement except an artificial form of a rare metal. let us bring into court an ornament of lombard architects, plate xii., fig. 7, as exclusively composed of right lines as the other, only, observe, with the noble element of shadow added. this ornament, taken from the front of the cathedral of pisa, is universal throughout the lombard churches of pisa, lucca, pistoja, and florence; and it will be a grave stain upon them if it cannot be defended. its first apology for itself, made in a hurry, sounds marvellously like the greek one, and highly dubious. it says that its terminal contour is the very image of a carefully prepared artificial crystal of common salt. salt being, however, a substance considerably more familiar to us than bismuth, the chances are somewhat in favor of the accused lombard ornament already. but it has more to say for itself, and more to the purpose; namely, that its main outline is one not only of natural crystallisation, but among the very first and commonest of crystalline forms, being the primal condition of the occurrence of the oxides of iron, copper, and tin, of the sulphurets of iron and lead, of fluor spar, &c.; and that those projecting forms in its surface represent the conditions of structure which effect the change into another relative and equally common crystalline form, the cube. this is quite enough. we may rest assured it is as good a combination of such simple right lines as can be put together, and gracefully fitted for every place in which such lines are necessary.

viii. the next ornament whose cause i would try is that of our tudor work, the portcullis. reticulation is common enough in natural form, and very beautiful; but it is either of the most delicate and gauzy texture, or of variously sized meshes and undulating lines. there is no family relation between portcullis and cobwebs or beetles' wings; something like it, perhaps, may be found in some kinds of crocodile armor and on the backs of the northern divers, but always beautifully varied in size of mesh. there is a dignity in the[pg 106] thing itself, if its size were exhibited, and the shade given through its bars; but even these merits are taken away in the tudor diminution of it, set on a solid surface. it has not a single syllable, i believe, to say in its defence. it is another monster, absolutely and unmitigatedly frightful. all that carving on henry the seventh's chapel simply deforms the stones of it.

in the same clause with the portcullis, we may condemn all heraldic decoration, so far as beauty is its object. its pride and significance have their proper place, fitly occurring in prominent parts of the building, as over its gates; and allowably in places where its legendary may be plainly read, as in painted windows, bosses of ceilings, &c. and sometimes, of course, the forms which it presents may be beautiful, as of animals, or simple symbols like the fleur-de-lis; but, for the most part, heraldic similitudes and arrangements are so professedly and pointedly unnatural, that it would be difficult to invent anything uglier; and the use of them as a repeated decoration will utterly destroy both the power and beauty of any building. common sense and courtesy also forbid their repetition. it is right to tell those who enter your doors that you are such a one, and of such a rank; but to tell it to them again and again, wherever they turn, becomes soon impertinence, and at last folly. let, therefore, the entire bearings occur in few places, and these not considered as an ornament, but as an inscription; and for frequent appliance, let any single and fair symbol be chosen out of them. thus we may multiply as much as we choose the french fleur-de-lis, or the florentine giglio bianco, or the english rose; but we must not multiply a king's arms.

ix. it will also follow, from these considerations, that if any one part of heraldic decoration be worse than another, it is the motto; since, of all things unlike nature, the forms of letters are, perhaps, the most so. even graphic tellurium and felspar look, at their clearest, anything but legible. all letters are, therefore, to be considered as frightful things, and to be endured only upon occasion; that is to say, in places where the sense of the inscription is of more importance than[pg 107] external ornament. inscriptions in churches, in rooms, and on pictures, are often desirable, but they are not to be considered as architectural or pictorial ornaments: they are, on the contrary, obstinate offences to the eye, not to be suffered except when their intellectual office introduces them. place them, therefore, where they will be read, and there only; and let them be plainly written, and not turned upside down, nor wrong end first. it is an ill sacrifice to beauty to make that illegible whose only merit is in its sense. write it as you would speak it, simply; and do not draw the eye to it when it would fain rest elsewhere, nor recommend your sentence by anything but a little openness of place and architectural silence about it. write the commandments on the church walls where they may be plainly seen, but do not put a dash and a tail to every letter; and remember that you are an architect, not a writing master.

x. inscriptions appear sometimes to be introduced for the sake of the scroll on which they are written; and in late and modern painted glass, as well as in architecture, these scrolls are flourished and turned hither and thither as if they were ornamental. ribands occur frequently in arabesques,—in some of a high order, too,—tying up flowers, or flitting in and out among the fixed forms. is there anything like ribands in nature? it might be thought that grass and sea-weed afforded apologetic types. they do not. there is a wide difference between their structure and that of a riband. they have a skeleton, an anatomy, a central rib, or fibre, or framework of some kind or another, which has a beginning and an end, a root and head, and whose make and strength effects every direction of their motion, and every line of their form. the loosest weed that drifts and waves under the heaving of the sea, or hangs heavily on the brown and slippery shore, has a marked strength, structure, elasticity, gradation of substance; its extremities are more finely fibred than its centre, its centre than its root; every fork of its ramification is measured and proportioned; every wave of its languid lines is love. it has its allotted size, and place, and function; it is a specific creature. what is there like this in a riband? it has[pg 108] no structure: it is a succession of cut threads all alike; it has no skeleton, no make, no form, no size, no will of its own. you cut it and crush it into what you will. it has no strength, no languor. it cannot fall into a single graceful form. it cannot wave, in the true sense, but only flutter: it cannot bend, in the true sense, but only turn and be wrinkled. it is a vile thing; it spoils all that is near its wretched film of an existence. never use it. let the flowers come loose if they cannot keep together without being tied; leave the sentence unwritten if you cannot write it on a tablet or book, or plain roll of paper. i know what authority there is against me. i remember the scrolls of perugino's angels, and the ribands of raphael's arabesques, and of ghiberti's glorious bronze flowers: no matter; they are every one of them vices and uglinesses. raphael usually felt this, and used an honest and rational tablet, as in the madonna di fuligno. i do not say there is any type of such tablets in nature, but all the difference lies in the fact that the tablet is not considered as an ornament, and the riband, or flying scroll, is. the tablet, as in albert durer's adam and eve, is introduced for the sake of the writing, understood and allowed as an ugly but necessary interruption. the scroll is extended as an ornamental form, which it is not, nor ever can be.

xi. but it will be said that all this want of organisation and form might be affirmed of drapery also, and that this latter is a noble subject of sculpture. by no means. when was drapery a subject of sculpture by itself, except in the form of a handkerchief on urns in the seventeenth century and in some of the baser scenic italian decorations? drapery, as such, is always ignoble; it becomes a subject of interest only by the colors it bears, and the impressions which it receives from some foreign form or force. all noble draperies, either in painting or sculpture (color and texture being at present out of our consideration), have, so far as they are anything more than necessities, one of two great functions; they are the exponents of motion and of gravitation. they are the most valuable means of expressing past as well as present motion in the figure, and they are almost the only means of[pg 109] indicating to the eye the force of gravity which resists such motion. the greeks used drapery in sculpture for the most part as an ugly necessity, but availed themselves of it gladly in all representation of action, exaggerating the arrangements of it which express lightness in the material, and follow gesture in the person. the christian sculptors, caring little for the body, or disliking it, and depending exclusively on the countenance, received drapery at first contentedly as a veil, but soon perceived a capacity of expression in it which the greek had not seen or had despised. the principal element of this expression was the entire removal of agitation from what was so pre-eminently capable of being agitated. it fell from their human forms plumb down, sweeping the ground heavily, and concealing the feet; while the greek drapery was often blown away from the thigh. the thick and coarse stuffs of the monkish dresses, so absolutely opposed to the thin and gauzy web of antique material, suggested simplicity of division as well as weight of fall. there was no crushing nor subdividing them. and thus the drapery gradually came to represent the spirit of repose as it before had of motion, repose saintly and severe. the wind had no power upon the garment, as the passion none upon the soul; and the motion of the figure only bent into a softer line the stillness of the falling veil, followed by it like a slow cloud by drooping rain: only in links of lighter undulation it followed the dances of the angels.

thus treated, drapery is indeed noble; but it is as an exponent of other and higher things. as that of gravitation, it has especial majesty, being literally the only means we have of fully representing this mysterious natural force of earth (for falling water is less passive and less defined in its lines). so, again, in sails it is beautiful because it receives the forms of solid curved surface, and expresses the force of another invisible element. but drapery trusted to its own merits, and given for its own sake,—drapery like that of carlo dolci and the caraccis,—is always base.

xii. closely connected with the abuse of scrolls and bands, is that of garlands and festoons of flowers as an architectural[pg 110] decoration, for unnatural arrangements are just as ugly as unnatural forms; and architecture, in borrowing the objects of nature, is bound to place them, as far as may be in her power, in such associations as may befit and express their origin. she is not to imitate directly the natural arrangement; she is not to carve irregular stems of ivy up her columns to account for the leaves at the top, but she is nevertheless to place her most exuberant vegetable ornament just where nature would have placed it, and to give some indication of that radical and connected structure which nature would have given it. thus the corinthian capital is beautiful, because it expands under the abacus just as nature would have expanded it; and because it looks as if the leaves had one root, though that root is unseen. and the flamboyant leaf mouldings are beautiful, because they nestle and run up the hollows, and fill the angles, and clasp the shafts which natural leaves would have delighted to fill and to clasp. they are no mere cast of natural leaves; they are counted, orderly, and architectural: but they are naturally, and therefore beautifully, placed.

xiii. now i do not mean to say that nature never uses festoons: she loves them, and uses them lavishly; and though she does so only in those places of excessive luxuriance wherein it seems to me that architectural types should seldom be sought, yet a falling tendril or pendent bough might, if managed with freedom and grace, be well introduced into luxuriant decoration (or if not, it is not their want of beauty, but of architectural fitness, which incapacitates them for such uses). but what resemblance to such example can we trace in a mass of all manner of fruit and flowers, tied heavily into a long bunch, thickest in the middle, and pinned up by both ends against a dead wall? for it is strange that the wildest and most fanciful of the builders of truly luxuriant architecture never ventured, so far as i know, even a pendent tendril; while the severest masters of the revived greek permitted this extraordinary piece of luscious ugliness to be fastened in the middle of their blank surfaces. so surely as this arrangement is adopted, the whole value of the flower work is lost. who among the crowds that gaze upon the building ever pause to[pg 111] admire the flower work of st. paul's? it is as careful and as rich as it can be, yet it adds no delightfulness to the edifice. it is no part of it. it is an ugly excrescence. we always conceive the building without it, and should be happier if our conception were not disturbed by its presence. it makes the rest of the architecture look poverty-stricken, instead of sublime; and yet it is never enjoyed itself. had it been put, where it ought, into the capitals, it would have been beheld with never-ceasing delight. i do not mean that it could have been so in the present building, for such kind of architecture has no business with rich ornament in any place; but that if those groups of flowers had been put into natural places in an edifice of another style, their value would have been felt as vividly as now their uselessness. what applies to festoons is still more sternly true of garlands. a garland is meant to be seen upon a head. there it is beautiful, because we suppose it newly gathered and joyfully worn. but it is not meant to be hung upon a wall. if you want a circular ornament, put a flat circle of colored marble, as in the casa doria and other such palaces at venice; or put a star, or a medallion, or if you want a ring, put a solid one, but do not carve the images of garlands, looking as if they had been used in the last procession, and been hung up to dry, and serve next time withered. why not also carve pegs, and hats upon them?

xiv. one of the worst enemies of modern gothic architecture, though seemingly an unimportant feature, is an excrescence, as offensive by its poverty as the garland by its profusion, the dripstone in the shape of the handle of a chest of drawers, which is used over the square-headed windows of what we call elizabethan buildings. in the last chapter, it will be remembered that the square form was shown to be that of pre-eminent power, and to be properly adapted and limited to the exhibition of space or surface. hence, when the window is to be an exponent of power, as for instance in those by m. angelo in the lower story of the palazzo ricardi at florence, the square head is the most noble form they can assume; but then either their space must be unbroken, and their associated mouldings the most severe, or else the square[pg 112] must be used as a finial outline, and is chiefly to be associated with forms of tracery, in which the relative form of power, the circle, is predominant, as in venetian, and florentine, and pisan gothic. but if you break upon your terminal square, or if you cut its lines off at the top and turn them outwards, you have lost its unity and space. it is an including form no longer, but an added, isolated line, and the ugliest possible. look abroad into the landscape and see if you can discover any one so bent and fragmentary as that of this strange windlass-looking dripstone. you cannot. it is a monster. it unites every element of ugliness, its line is harshly broken in itself, and unconnected with every other; it has no harmony either with structure or decoration, it has no architectural support, it looks glued to the wall, and the only pleasant property it has, is the appearance of some likelihood of its dropping off.

i might proceed, but the task is a weary one, and i think i have named those false forms of decoration which are most dangerous in our modern architecture as being legal and accepted. the barbarisms of individual fancy are as countless as they are contemptible; they neither admit attack nor are worth it; but these above named are countenanced, some by the practice of antiquity, all by high authority: they have depressed the proudest, and contaminated the purest schools, and are so established in recent practice that i write rather for the barren satisfaction of bearing witness against them, than with hope of inducing any serious convictions to their prejudice.

xv. thus far of what is not ornament. what ornament is, will without difficulty be determined by the application of the same test. it must consist of such studious arrangements of form as are imitative or suggestive of those which are commonest among natural existences, that being of course the noblest ornament which represents the highest orders of existence. imitated flowers are nobler than imitated stones, imitated animals, than flowers; imitated human form of all animal forms the noblest. but all are combined in the richest ornamental work; and the rock, the fountain, the flowing river with its pebbled bed, the sea, the clouds of[pg 113] heaven, the herb of the field, the fruit-tree bearing fruit, the creeping thing, the bird, the beast, the man, and the angel, mingle their fair forms on the bronze of ghiberti.

every thing being then ornamental that is imitative, i would ask the reader's attention to a few general considerations, all that can here be offered relating to so vast a subject; which, for convenience sake, may be classed under the three heads of inquiry:—what is the right place for architectural ornament? what is the peculiar treatment of ornament which renders it architectural? and what is the right use of color as associated with architectural imitative form?

xvi. what is the place of ornament? consider first that the characters of natural objects which the architect can represent are few and abstract. the greater part of those delights by which nature recommends herself to man at all times, cannot be conveyed by him into his imitative work. he cannot make his grass green and cool and good to rest upon, which in nature is its chief use to man; nor can he make his flowers tender and full of color and of scent, which in nature are their chief powers of giving joy. those qualities which alone he can secure are certain severe characters of form, such as men only see in nature on deliberate examination, and by the full and set appliance of sight and thought: a man must lie down on the bank of grass on his breast and set himself to watch and penetrate the intertwining of it, before he finds that which is good to be gathered by the architect. so then while nature is at all times pleasant to us, and while the sight and sense of her work may mingle happily with all our thoughts, and labors, and times of existence, that image of her which the architect carries away represents what we can only perceive in her by direct intellectual exertion, and demands from us, wherever it appears, an intellectual exertion of a similar kind in order to understand it and feel it. it is the written or sealed impression of a thing sought out, it is the shaped result of inquiry and bodily expression of thought.

xvii. now let us consider for an instant what would be the effect of continually repeating an expression of a beautiful[pg 114] thought to any other of the senses at times when the mind could not address that sense to the understanding of it. suppose that in time of serious occupation, of stern business, a companion should repeat in our ears continually some favorite passage of poetry, over and over again all day long. we should not only soon be utterly sick and weary of the sound of it, but that sound would at the end of the day have so sunk into the habit of the ear that the entire meaning of the passage would be dead to us, and it would ever thenceforward require some effort to fix and recover it. the music of it would not meanwhile have aided the business in hand, while its own delightfulness would thenceforward be in a measure destroyed. it is the same with every other form of definite thought. if you violently present its expression to the senses, at times when the mind is otherwise engaged, that expression will be ineffective at the time, and will have its sharpness and clearness destroyed forever. much more if you present it to the mind at times when it is painfully affected or disturbed, or if you associate the expression of pleasant thought with incongruous circumstances, you will affect that expression thenceforward with a painful color for ever.

xviii. apply this to expressions of thought received by the eye. remember that the eye is at your mercy more than the ear. "the eye it cannot choose but see." its nerve is not so easily numbed as that of the ear, and it is often busied in tracing and watching forms when the ear is at rest. now if you present lovely forms to it when it cannot call the mind to help it in its work, and among objects of vulgar use and unhappy position, you will neither please the eye nor elevate the vulgar object. but you will fill and weary the eye with the beautiful form, and you will infect that form itself with the vulgarity of the thing to which you have violently attached it. it will never be of much use to you any more; you have killed or defiled it; its freshness and purity are gone. you will have to pass it through the fire of much thought before you will cleanse it, and warm it with much love before it will revive.[pg 115]

xix. hence then a general law, of singular importance in the present day, a law of simple common sense,—not to decorate things belonging to purposes of active and occupied life. wherever you can rest, there decorate; where rest is forbidden, so is beauty. you must not mix ornament with business, any more than you may mix play. work first, and then rest. work first and then gaze, but do not use golden ploughshares, nor bind ledgers in enamel. do not thrash with sculptured flails: nor put bas-reliefs on millstones. what! it will be asked, are we in the habit of doing so? even so; always and everywhere. the most familiar position of greek mouldings is in these days on shop fronts. there is not a tradesman's sign nor shelf nor counter in all the streets of all our cities, which has not upon it ornaments which were invented to adorn temples and beautify kings' palaces. there is not the smallest advantage in them where they are. absolutely valueless—utterly without the power of giving pleasure, they only satiate the eye, and vulgarise their own forms. many of these are in themselves thoroughly good copies of fine things, which things themselves we shall never, in consequence, enjoy any more. many a pretty beading and graceful bracket there is in wood or stucco above our grocers' and cheese-mongers' and hosiers' shops: how it is that the tradesmen cannot understand that custom is to be had only by selling good tea and cheese and cloth, and that people come to them for their honesty, and their readiness, and their right wares, and not because they have greek cornices over their windows, or their names in large gilt letters on their house fronts? how pleasurable it would be to have the power of going through the streets of london, pulling down those brackets and friezes and large names, restoring to the tradesmen the capital they had spent in architecture, and putting them on honest and equal terms, each with his name in black letters over his door, not shouted down the street from the upper stories, and each with a plain wooden shop casement, with small panes in it that people would not think of breaking in order to be sent to prison! how much better for them would it be—how much[pg 116] happier, how much wiser, to put their trust upon their own truth and industry, and not on the idiocy of their customers. it is curious, and it says little for our national probity on the one hand, or prudence on the other, to see the whole system of our street decoration based on the idea that people must be baited to a shop as moths are to a candle.

xx. but it will be said that much of the best wooden decoration of the middle ages was in shop fronts. no; it was in house fronts, of which the shop was a part, and received its natural and consistent portion of the ornament. in those days men lived, and intended to live by their shops, and over them, all their days. they were contented with them and happy in them: they were their palaces and castles. they gave them therefore such decoration as made themselves happy in their own habitation, and they gave it for their own sake. the upper stories were always the richest, and the shop was decorated chiefly about the door, which belonged to the house more than to it. and when our tradesmen settle to their shops in the same way, and form no plans respecting future villa architecture, let their whole houses be decorated, and their shops too, but with a national and domestic decoration (i shall speak more of this point in the sixth chapter). however, our cities are for the most part too large to admit of contented dwelling in them throughout life; and i do not say there is harm in our present system of separating the shop from the dwelling-house; only where they are so separated, let us remember that the only reason for shop decoration is removed, and see that the decoration be removed also.

xxi. another of the strange and evil tendencies of the present day is to the decoration of the railroad station. now, if there be any place in the world in which people are deprived of that portion of temper and discretion which are necessary to the contemplation of beauty, it is there. it is the very temple of discomfort, and the only charity that the builder can extend to us is to show us, plainly as may be, how soonest to escape from it. the whole system of railroad travelling is addressed to people who, being in a hurry, are there[pg 117]fore, for the time being, miserable. no one would travel in that manner who could help it—who had time to go leisurely over hills and between hedges, instead of through tunnels and between banks: at least those who would, have no sense of beauty so acute as that we need consult it at the station. the railroad is in all its relations a matter of earnest business, to be got through as soon as possible. it transmutes a man from a traveller into a living parcel. for the time he has parted with the nobler characteristics of his humanity for the sake of a planetary power of locomotion. do not ask him to admire anything. you might as well ask the wind. carry him safely, dismiss him soon: he will thank you for nothing else. all attempts to please him in any other way are mere mockery, and insults to the things by which you endeavor to do so. there never was more flagrant nor impertinent folly than the smallest portion of ornament in anything concerned with railroads or near them. keep them out of the way, take them through the ugliest country you can find, confess them the miserable things they are, and spend nothing upon them but for safety and speed. give large salaries to efficient servants, large prices to good manufacturers, large wages to able workmen; let the iron be tough, and the brickwork solid, and the carriages strong. the time is perhaps not distant when these first necessities may not be easily met: and to increase expense in any other direction is madness. better bury gold in the embankments, than put it in ornaments on the stations. will a single traveller be willing to pay an increased fare on the south western, because the columns of the terminus are covered with patterns from nineveh? he will only care less for the ninevite ivories in the british museum: or on the north western, because there are old english-looking spandrils to the roof of the station at crewe? he will only have less pleasure in their prototypes at crewe house. railroad architecture has or would have a dignity of its own if it were only left to its work. you would not put rings on the fingers of a smith at his anvil.

xxii. it is not however only in these marked situations that the abuse of which i speak takes place. there is hardly,[pg 118] at present, an application of ornamental work, which is not in some sort liable to blame of the same kind. we have a bad habit of trying to disguise disagreeable necessities by some form of sudden decoration, which is, in all other places, associated with such necessities. i will name only one instance, that to which i have alluded before—the roses which conceal the ventilators in the flat roofs of our chapels. many of those roses are of very beautiful design, borrowed from fine works: all their grace and finish are invisible when they are so placed, but their general form is afterwards associated with the ugly buildings in which they constantly occur; and all the beautiful roses of the early french and english gothic, especially such elaborate ones as those of the triforium of coutances, are in consequence deprived of their pleasurable influence: and this without our having accomplished the smallest good by the use we have made of the dishonored form. not a single person in the congregation ever receives one ray of pleasure from those roof roses; they are regarded with mere indifference, or lost in the general impression of harsh emptiness.

xxiii. must not beauty, then, it will be asked, be sought for in the forms which we associate with our every-day life? yes, if you do it consistently, and in places where it can be calmly seen; but not if you use the beautiful form only as a mask and covering of the proper conditions and uses of things, nor if you thrust it into the places set apart for toil. put it in the drawing-room, not into the workshop; put it upon domestic furniture, not upon tools of handicraft. all men have sense of what is right in this manner, if they would only use and apply that sense; every man knows where and how beauty gives him pleasure, if he would only ask for it when it does so, and not allow it to be forced upon him when he does not want it. ask any one of the passengers over london bridge at this instant whether he cares about the forms of the bronze leaves on its lamps, and he will tell you, no. modify these forms of leaves to a less scale, and put them on his milk-jug at breakfast, and ask him whether he likes them, and he will tell you, yes. people have no need of teaching if they[pg 119] could only think and speak truth, and ask for what they like and want, and for nothing else: nor can a right disposition of beauty be ever arrived at except by this common sense, and allowance for the circumstances of the time and place. it does not follow, because bronze leafage is in bad taste on the lamps of london bridge, that it would be so on those of the ponte della trinita; nor, because it would be a folly to decorate the house fronts of gracechurch street, that it would be equally so to adorn those of some quiet provincial town. the question of greatest external or internal decoration depends entirely on the conditions of probable repose. it was a wise feeling which made the streets of venice so rich in external ornament, for there is no couch of rest like the gondola. so, again, there is no subject of street ornament so wisely chosen as the fountain, where it is a fountain of use; for it is just there that perhaps the happiest pause takes place in the labor of the day, when the pitcher is rested on the edge of it, and the breath of the bearer is drawn deeply, and the hair swept from the forehead, and the uprightness of the form declined against the marble ledge, and the sound of the kind word or light laugh mixes with the trickle of the falling water, heard shriller and shriller as the pitcher fills. what pause is so sweet as that—so full of the depth of ancient days, so softened with the calm of pastoral solitude?

xxiv. ii. thus far, then, of the place for beauty. we were next to inquire into the characters which fitted it peculiarly for architectural appliance, and into the principles of choice and of arrangement which best regulate the imitation of natural forms in which it consists. the full answering of these questions would be a treatise on the art of design: i intend only to say a few words respecting the two conditions of that art which are essentially architectural,—proportion and abstraction. neither of these qualities is necessary, to the same extent, in other fields of design. the sense of proportion is, by the landscape painter, frequently sacrificed to character and accident; the power of abstraction to that of complete realisation. the flowers of his foreground must often be unmeasured in their quantity, loose in their arrangement: what[pg 120] is calculated, either in quantity or disposition, must be artfully concealed. that calculation is by the architect to be prominently exhibited. so the abstraction of few characteristics out of many is shown only in the painter's sketch; in his finished work it is concealed or lost in completion. architecture, on the contrary, delights in abstraction and fears to complete her forms. proportion and abstraction, then, are the two especial marks of architectural design as distinguished from all other. sculpture must have them in inferior degrees; leaning, on the one hand, to an architectural manner, when it is usually greatest (becoming, indeed, a part of architecture), and, on the other, to a pictorial manner, when it is apt to lose its dignity, and sink into mere ingenious carving.

xxv. now, of proportion so much has been written, that i believe the only facts which are of practical use have been overwhelmed and kept out of sight by vain accumulations of particular instances and estimates. proportions are as infinite (and that in all kinds of things, as severally in colors, lines, shades, lights, and forms) as possible airs in music: and it is just as rational an attempt to teach a young architect how to proportion truly and well by calculating for him the proportions of fine works, as it would be to teach him to compose melodies by calculating the mathematical relations of the notes in beethoven's adela?de or mozart's requiem. the man who has eye and intellect will invent beautiful proportions, and cannot help it; but he can no more tell us how to do it than wordsworth could tell us how to write a sonnet, or than scott could have told us how to plan a romance. but there are one or two general laws which can be told: they are of no use, indeed, except as preventives of gross mistake, but they are so far worth telling and remembering; and the more so because, in the discussion of the subtle laws of proportion (which will never be either numbered or known), architects are perpetually forgetting and transgressing the very simplest of its necessities.

xxvi. of which the first is, that wherever proportion exists at all, one member of the composition must be either larger than, or in some way supreme over, the rest. there is no[pg 121] proportion between equal things. they can have symmetry only, and symmetry without proportion is not composition. it is necessary to perfect beauty, but it is the least necessary of its elements, nor of course is there any difficulty in obtaining it. any succession of equal things is agreeable; but to compose is to arrange unequal things, and the first thing to be done in beginning a composition is to determine which is to be the principal thing. i believe that all that has been written and taught about proportion, put together, is not to the architect worth the single rule, well enforced, "have one large thing and several smaller things, or one principal thing and several inferior things, and bind them well together." sometimes there may be a regular gradation, as between the heights of stories in good designs for houses; sometimes a monarch with a lowly train, as in the spire with its pinnacles: the varieties of arrangement are infinite, but the law is universal—have one thing above the rest, either by size, or office, or interest. don't put the pinnacles without the spire. what a host of ugly church towers have we in england, with pinnacles at the corners, and none in the middle! how many buildings like king's college chapel at cambridge, looking like tables upside down, with their four legs in the air! what! it will be said, have not beasts four legs? yes, but legs of different shapes, and with a head between them. so they have a pair of ears: and perhaps a pair of horns: but not at both ends. knock down a couple of pinnacles at either end in king's college chapel, and you will have a kind of proportion instantly. so in a cathedral you may have one tower in the centre, and two at the west end; or two at the west end only, though a worse arrangement: but you must not have two at the west and two at the east end, unless you have some central member to connect them; and even then, buildings are generally bad which have large balancing features at the extremities, and small connecting ones in the centre, because it is not easy then to make the centre dominant. the bird or moth may indeed have wide wings, because the size of the wing does not give supremacy to the wing. the head and life are the mighty things, and the plumes, however wide, are sub[pg 122]ordinate. in fine west fronts with a pediment and two towers, the centre is always the principal mass, both in bulk and interest (as having the main gateway), and the towers are subordinated to it, as an animal's horns are to its head. the moment the towers rise so high as to overpower the body and centre, and become themselves the principal masses, they will destroy the proportion, unless they are made unequal, and one of them the leading feature of the cathedral, as at antwerp and strasburg. but the purer method is to keep them down in due relation to the centre, and to throw up the pediment into a steep connecting mass, drawing the eye to it by rich tracery. this is nobly done in st. wulfran of abbeville, and attempted partly at rouen, though that west front is made up of so many unfinished and supervening designs that it is impossible to guess the real intention of any one of its builders.

plate x. plate x.—(page 122—vol. v.)

traceries and mouldings from rouen and salisbury.

xxvii. this rule of supremacy applies to the smallest as well as to the leading features: it is interestingly seen in the arrangement of all good mouldings. i have given one, on the opposite page, from rouen cathedral; that of the tracery before distinguished as a type of the noblest manner of northern gothic (chap. ii. § xxii.). it is a tracery of three orders, of which the first is divided into a leaf moulding, fig. 4, and b in the section, and a plain roll, also seen in fig. 4, c in the section; these two divisions surround the entire window or panelling, and are carried by two-face shafts of corresponding sections. the second and third orders are plain rolls following the line of the tracery; four divisions of moulding in all: of these four, the leaf moulding is, as seen in the sections, much the largest; next to it the outer roll; then, by an exquisite alternation, the innermost roll (e), in order that it may not be lost in the recess and the intermediate (d), the smallest. each roll has its own shaft and capital; and the two smaller, which in effect upon the eye, owing to the retirement of the innermost, are nearly equal, have smaller capitals than the two larger, lifted a little to bring them to the same level. the wall in the trefoiled lights is curved, as from e to f in the section; but in the quatrefoil it is flat, only thrown back to the full depth of the recess below so as to get a sharp shadow [pg 123] instead of a soft one, the mouldings falling back to it in nearly a vertical curve behind the roll e. this could not, however, be managed with the simpler mouldings of the smaller quatrefoil above, whose half section is given from g to g2; but the architect was evidently fretted by the heavy look of its circular foils as opposed to the light spring of the arches below: so he threw its cusps obliquely clear from the wall, as seen in fig. 2, attached to it where they meet the circle, but with their finials pushed out from the natural level (h, in the section) to that of the first order (g2) and supported by stone props behind, as seen in the profile fig. 2, which i got from the correspondent panel on the buttress face (fig. 1 being on its side), and of which the lower cusps, being broken away, show the remnant of one of their props projecting from the wall. the oblique curve thus obtained in the profile is of singular grace. take it all in all, i have never met with a more exquisite piece of varied, yet severe, proportioned and general arrangement (though all the windows of the period are fine, and especially delightful in the subordinate proportioning of the smaller capitals to the smaller shafts). the only fault it has is the inevitable misarrangement of the central shafts; for the enlargement of the inner roll, though beautiful in the group of four divisions at the side, causes, in the triple central shaft, the very awkwardness of heavy lateral members which has just been in most instances condemned. in the windows of the choir, and in most of the period, this difficulty is avoided by making the fourth order a fillet which only follows the foliation, while the three outermost are nearly in arithmetical progression of size, and the central triple shaft has of course the largest roll in front. the moulding of the palazzo foscari (plate viii., and plate iv. fig. 8) is, for so simple a group, the grandest in effect i have even seen: it is composed of a large roll with two subordinates.

xxviii. it is of course impossible to enter into details of instances belonging to so intricate division of our subject, in the compass of a general essay. i can but rapidly name the chief conditions of right. another of these is the connection[pg 124] of symmetry with horizontal, and of proportion with vertical, division. evidently there is in symmetry a sense not merely of equality, but of balance: now a thing cannot be balanced by another on the top of it, though it may by one at the side of it. hence, while it is not only allowable, but often necessary, to divide buildings, or parts of them, horizontally into halves, thirds, or other equal parts, all vertical divisions of this kind are utterly wrong; worst into half, next worst in the regular numbers which more betray the equality. i should have thought this almost the first principle of proportion which a young architect was taught: and yet i remember an important building, recently erected in england, in which the columns are cut in half by the projecting architraves of the central windows; and it is quite usual to see the spires of modern gothic churches divided by a band of ornament half way up. in all fine spires there are two bands and three parts, as at salisbury. the ornamented portion of the tower is there cut in half, and allowably, because the spire forms the third mass to which the other two are subordinate: two stories are also equal in giotto's campanile, but dominant over smaller divisions below, and subordinated to the noble third above. even this arrangement is difficult to treat; and it is usually safer to increase or diminish the height of the divisions regularly as they rise, as in the doge's palace, whose three divisions are in a bold geometrical progression: or, in towers, to get an alternate proportion between the body, the belfry, and the crown, as in the campanile of st. mark's. but, at all events, get rid of equality; leave that to children and their card houses: the laws of nature and the reason of man are alike against it, in arts, as in politics. there is but one thoroughly ugly tower in italy that i know of, and that is so because it is divided into vertical equal parts: the tower of pisa.12

xxix. one more principle of proportion i have to name, equally simple, equally neglected. proportion is between three terms at least. hence, as the pinnacles are not enough without the spire, so neither the spire without the pinnacles. all men feel this and usually express their feeling by saying that[pg 125] the pinnacles conceal the junction of the spire and tower. this is one reason; but a more influential one is, that the pinnacles furnish the third term to the spire and tower. so that it is not enough, in order to secure proportion, to divide a building unequally; it must be divided into at least three parts; it may be into more (and in details with advantage), but on a large scale i find three is about the best number of parts in elevation, and five in horizontal extent, with freedom of increase to five in the one case and seven in the other; but not to more without confusion (in architecture, that is to say; for in organic structure the numbers cannot be limited). i purpose, in the course of works which are in preparation, to give copious illustrations of this subject, but i will take at present only one instance of vertical proportion, from the flower stem of the common water plantain, alisma plantago. fig. 5, plate xii. is a reduced profile of one side of a plant gathered at random; it is seen to have five masts, of which, however, the uppermost is a mere shoot, and we can consider only their relations up to the fourth. their lengths are measured on the line a b, which is the actual length of the lowest mass a b, a c=b c, a d=c d, and a e=d e. if the reader will take the trouble to measure these lengths and compare them, he will find that, within half a line, the uppermost a e=5/7 of a d, a d=6/8 of a c, and a c=7/9 of a b; a most subtle diminishing proportion. from each of the joints spring three major and three minor branches, each between each; but the major branches, at any joint, are placed over the minor branches at the joint below, by the curious arrangement of the joint itself—the stem is bluntly triangular; fig. 6 shows the section of any joint. the outer darkened triangle is the section of the lower stem; the inner, left light, of the upper stem; and the three main branches spring from the ledges left by the recession. thus the stems diminish in diameter just as they diminish in height. the main branches (falsely placed in the profile over each other to show their relations) have respectively seven, six, five, four, and three arm-bones, like the masts of the stem; these divisions being proportioned in the same subtle manner. from the joints of[pg 126] these, it seems to be the plan of the plant that three major and three minor branches should again spring, bearing the flowers: but, in these infinitely complicated members, vegetative nature admits much variety; in the plant from which these measures were taken the full complement appeared only at one of the secondary joints.

the leaf of this plant has five ribs on each side, as its flower generally five masts, arranged with the most exquisite grace of curve; but of lateral proportion i shall rather take illustrations from architecture: the reader will find several in the accounts of the duomo at pisa and st. mark's at venice, in chap. v. §§ xiv.-xvi. i give these arrangements merely as illustrations, not as precedents: all beautiful proportions are unique, they are not general formul?.

xxx. the other condition of architectural treatment which we proposed to notice was the abstraction of imitated form. but there is a peculiar difficulty in touching within these narrow limits on such a subject as this, because the abstraction of which we find examples in existing art, is partly involuntary; and it is a matter of much nicety to determine where it begins to be purposed. in the progress of national as well as of individual mind, the first attempts at imitation are always abstract and incomplete. greater completion marks the progress of art, absolute completion usually its decline; whence absolute completion of imitative form is often supposed to be in itself wrong. but it is not wrong always, only dangerous. let us endeavor briefly to ascertain wherein its danger consists, and wherein its dignity.

xxxi. i have said that all art is abstract in its beginnings; that is to say, it expresses only a small number of the qualities of the thing represented. curved and complex lines are represented by straight and simple ones; interior markings of forms are few, and much is symbolical and conventional. there is a resemblance between the work of a great nation, in this phase, and the work of childhood and ignorance, which, in the mind of a careless observer, might attach something like ridicule to it. the form of a tree on the ninevite sculptures is much like that which, come twenty years ago, was familiar upon samplers; and[pg 127] the types of the face and figure in early italian art are susceptible of easy caricature. on the signs which separate the infancy of magnificent manhood from every other, i do not pause to insist (they consist entirely in the choice of the symbol and of the features abstracted); but i pass to the next stage of art, a condition of strength in which the abstraction which was begun in incapability is continued in free will. this is the case, however, in pure sculpture and painting, as well as in architecture; and we have nothing to do but with that greater severity of manner which fits either to be associated with the more realist art. i believe it properly consists only in a due expression of their subordination, an expression varying according to their place and office. the question is first to be clearly determined whether the architecture is a frame for the sculpture, or the sculpture an ornament of the architecture. if the latter, then the first office of that sculpture is not to represent the things it imitates, but to gather out of them those arrangements of form which shall be pleasing to the eye in their intended places. so soon as agreeable lines and points of shade have been added to the mouldings which were meagre, or to the lights which were unrelieved, the architectural work of the imitation is accomplished; and how far it shall be wrought towards completeness or not, will depend upon its place, and upon other various circumstances. if, in its particular use or position, it is symmetrically arranged, there is, of course, an instant indication of architectural subjection. but symmetry is not abstraction. leaves may be carved in the most regular order, and yet be meanly imitative; or, on the other hand, they may be thrown wild and loose, and yet be highly architectural in their separate treatment. nothing can be less symmetrical than the group of leaves which join the two columns in plate xiii.; yet, since nothing of the leaf character is given but what is necessary for the bare suggestion of its image and the attainment of the lines desired, their treatment is highly abstract. it shows that the workman only wanted so much of the leaf as he supposed good for his architecture, and would allow no more; and how much is to be supposed good, depends, as i have said, much more on place and circumstance than on general laws. i know[pg 128] that this is not usually thought, and that many good architects would insist on abstraction in all cases: the question is so wide and so difficult that i express my opinion upon it most diffidently; but my own feeling is, that a purely abstract manner, like that of our earliest english work, does not afford room for the perfection of beautiful form, and that its severity is wearisome after the eye has been long accustomed to it. i have not done justice to the salisbury dog-tooth moulding, of which the effect is sketched in fig. 5, plate x., but i have done more justice to it nevertheless than to the beautiful french one above it; and i do not think that any candid reader would deny that, piquant and spirited as is that from salisbury, the rouen moulding is, in every respect, nobler. it will be observed that its symmetry is more complicated, the leafage being divided into double groups of two lobes each, each lobe of different structure. with exquisite feeling, one of these double groups is alternately omitted on the other side of the moulding (not seen in the plate, but occupying the cavetto of the section), thus giving a playful lightness to the whole; and if the reader will allow for a beauty in the flow of the curved outlines (especially on the angle), of which he cannot in the least judge from my rude drawing, he will not, i think, expect easily to find a nobler instance of decoration adapted to the severest mouldings.

now it will be observed, that there is in its treatment a high degree of abstraction, though not so conventional as that of salisbury: that is to say, the leaves have little more than their flow and outline represented; they are hardly undercut, but their edges are connected by a gentle and most studied curve with the stone behind; they have no serrations, no veinings, no rib or stalk on the angle, only an incision gracefully made towards their extremities, indicative of the central rib and depression. the whole style of the abstraction shows that the architect could, if he had chosen, have carried the imitation much farther, but stayed at this point of his own free will; and what he has done is also so perfect in its kind, that i feel disposed to accept his authority without question, so far as i can gather it from his works, on the whole subject of abstraction.[pg 129]

xxxii. happily his opinion is frankly expressed. this moulding is on the lateral buttress, and on a level with the top of the north gate; it cannot therefore be closely seen except from the wooden stairs of the belfry; it is not intended to be so seen, but calculated for a distance of, at least, forty to fifty feet from the eye. in the vault of the gate itself, half as near again, there are three rows of mouldings, as i think, by the same designer, at all events part of the same plan. one of them is given in plate i. fig. 2 a. it will be seen that the abstraction is here infinitely less; the ivy leaves have stalks and associated fruit, and a rib for each lobe, and are so far undercut as to detach their forms from the stone; while in the vine-leaf moulding above, of the same period, from the south gate, serration appears added to other purely imitative characters. finally, in the animals which form the ornaments of the portion of the gate which is close to the eye, abstraction nearly vanishes into perfect sculpture.

xxxiii. nearness to the eye, however, is not the only circumstance which influences architectural abstraction. these very animals are not merely better cut because close to the eye; they are put close to the eye that they may, without indiscretion, be better cut, on the noble principle, first i think, clearly enunciated by mr. eastlake, that the closest imitation shall be of the noblest object. farther, since the wildness and manner of growth of vegetation render a bona fide imitation of it impossible in sculpture—since its members must be reduced in number, ordered in direction, and cut away from their roots, even under the most earnestly imitative treatment,—it becomes a point, as i think, of good judgment, to proportion the completeness of execution of parts to the formality of the whole; and since five or six leaves must stand for a tree, to let also five or six touches stand for a leaf. but since the animal generally admits of perfect outline—since its form is detached, and may be fully represented, its sculpture may be more complete and faithful in all its parts. and this principle will be actually found. i believe, to guide the old workmen. if the animal form be in a gargoyle, incomplete, and coining out of a block of stone, or if a head only, as for a boss[pg 130] or other such partial use, its sculpture will be highly abstract. but if it be an entire animal, as a lizard, or a bird, or a squirrel, peeping among leafage, its sculpture will be much farther carried, and i think, if small, near the eye, and worked in a fine material, may rightly be carried to the utmost possible completion. surely we cannot wish a less finish bestowed on those which animate the mouldings of the south door of the cathedral of florence; nor desire that the birds in the capitals of the doge's palace should be stripped of a single plume.

xxxiv. under these limitations, then, i think that perfect sculpture may be made a part of the severest architecture; but this perfection was said in the outset to be dangerous. it is so in the highest degree; for the moment the architect allows himself to dwell on the imitated portions, there is a chance of his losing sight of the duty of his ornament, of its business as a part of the composition, and sacrificing its points of shade and effect to the delight of delicate carving. and then he is lost. his architecture has become a mere framework for the setting of delicate sculpture, which had better be all taken down and put into cabinets. it is well, therefore, that the young architect should be taught to think of imitative ornament as of the extreme of grace in language; not to be regarded at first, not to be obtained at the cost of purpose, meaning, force, or conciseness, yet, indeed, a perfection—the least of all perfections, and yet the crowning one of all—one which by itself, and regarded in itself, is an architectural coxcombry, but is yet the sign of the most highly-trained mind and power when it is associated with others. it is a safe manner, as i think, to design all things at first in severe abstraction, and to be prepared, if need were, to carry them out in that form; then to mark the parts where high finish would be admissible, to complete these always with stern reference to their general effect, and then connect them by a graduated scale of abstraction with the rest. and there is one safeguard against danger in this process on which i would finally insist. never imitate anything but natural forms, and those the noblest, in the completed parts. the [pg 131] degradation of the cinque cento manner of decoration was not owing to its naturalism, to its faithfulness of imitation, but to its imitation of ugly, i.e. unnatural things. so long as it restrained itself to sculpture of animals and flowers, it remained noble. the balcony, on the opposite page, from a house in the campo st. benedetto at venice, shows one of the earliest occurrences of the cinque cento arabesque, and a fragment of the pattern is given in plate xii. fig. 8. it is but the arresting upon the stone work of a stem or two of the living flowers, which are rarely wanting in the window above (and which, by the by, the french and italian peasantry often trellis with exquisite taste about their casements). this arabesque, relieved as it is in darkness from the white stone by the stain of time, is surely both beautiful and pure; and as long as the renaissance ornament remained in such forms it may be beheld with undeserved admiration. but the moment that unnatural objects were associated with these, and armor, and musical instruments, and wild meaningless scrolls and curled shields, and other such fancies, became principal in its subjects, its doom was sealed, and with it that of the architecture of the world.

plate xi. plate xi.—(page 131—vol. v.)

balcony in the campo, st. benedetto, venice.

xxxv. iii. our final inquiry was to be into the use of color as associated with architectural ornament.

i do not feel able to speak with any confidence respecting the touching of sculpture with color. i would only note one point, that sculpture is the representation of an idea, while architecture is itself a real thing. the idea may, as i think, be left colorless, and colored by the beholder's mind: but a reality ought to have reality in all its attributes: its color should be as fixed as its form. i cannot, therefore, consider architecture as in any wise perfect without color. farther, as i have above noticed, i think the colors of architecture should be those of natural stones; partly because more durable, but also because more perfect and graceful. for to conquer the harshness and deadness of tones laid upon stone or on gesso, needs the management and discretion of a true painter; and on this co-operation we must not calculate in laying down rules for general practice. if tintoret or giorgione are at hand, and ask us for a wall to paint, we will alter our whole design[pg 132] for their sake, and become their servants; but we must, as architects, expect the aid of the common workman only; and the laying of color by a mechanical hand, and its toning under a vulgar eye, are far more offensive than rudeness in cutting the stone. the latter is imperfection only; the former deadness or discordance. at the best, such color is so inferior to the lovely and mellow hues of the natural stone, that it is wise to sacrifice some of the intricacy of design, if by so doing we may employ the nobler material. and if, as we looked to nature for instruction respecting form, we look to her also to learn the management of color, we shall, perhaps, find that this sacrifice of intricacy is for other causes expedient.

xxxvi. first, then, i think that in making this reference we are to consider our building as a kind of organized creature; in coloring which we must look to the single and separately organized creatures of nature, not to her landscape combinations. our building, if it is well composed, is one thing, and is to be colored as nature would color one thing—a shell, a flower, or an animal; not as she colors groups of things.

and the first broad conclusion we shall deduce from observance of natural color in such cases will be, that it never follows form, but is arranged on an entirely separate system. what mysterious connection there may be between the shape of the spots on an animal's skin and its anatomical system, i do not know, nor even if such a connection has in any wise been traced: but to the eye the systems are entirely separate, and in many cases that of color is accidentally variable. the stripes of a zebra do not follow the lines of its body or limbs, still less the spots of a leopard. in the plumage of birds, each feather bears a part of the pattern which is arbitrarily carried over the body, having indeed certain graceful harmonies with the form, diminishing or enlarging in directions which sometimes follow, but also not unfrequently oppose, the directions of its muscular lines. whatever harmonies there may be, are distinctly like those of two separate musical parts, coinciding here and there only—never discordant, but essentially different i hold this, then, for the first great principle[pg 133] of architectural color. let it be visibly independent of form. never paint a column with vertical lines, but always cross it.13 never give separate mouldings separate colors (i know this is heresy, but i never shrink from any conclusions, however contrary to human authority, to which i am led by observance of natural principles); and in sculptured ornaments i do not paint the leaves or figures (i cannot help the elgin frieze) of one color and their ground of another, but vary both the ground and the figures with the same harmony. notice how nature does it in a variegated flower; not one leaf red and another white, but a point of red and a zone of white, or whatever it may be, to each. in certain places you may run your two systems closer, and here and there let them be parallel for a note or two, but see that the colors and the forms coincide only as two orders of mouldings do; the same for an instant, but each holding its own course. so single members may sometimes have single colors: as a bird's head is sometimes of one color and its shoulders another, you may make your capital of one color and your shaft another; but in general the best place for color is on broad surfaces, not on the points of interest in form. an animal is mottled on its breast and back, rarely on its paws or about its eyes; so put your variegation boldly on the flat wall and broad shaft, but be shy of it in the capital and moulding; in all cases it is a safe rule to simplify color when form is rich, and vice versa; and i think it would be well in general to carve all capitals and graceful ornaments in white marble, and so leave them.

xxxvii. independence then being first secured, what kind of limiting outlines shall we adopt for the system of color itself?

i am quite sure that any person familiar with natural objects will never be surprised at any appearance of care or finish in them. that is the condition of the universe. but there is cause both for surprise and inquiry whenever we see anything like carelessness or incompletion: that is not a common condition; it must be one appointed for some singular purpose. i believe that such surprise will be forcibly felt by any one who, after studying carefully the lines of some variegated organic[pg 134] form, will set himself to copy with similar diligence those of its colors. the boundaries of the forms he will assuredly, whatever the object, have found drawn with a delicacy and precision which no human hand can follow. those of its colors he will find in many cases, though governed always by a certain rude symmetry, yet irregular, blotched, imperfect, liable to all kinds of accidents and awkwardnesses. look at the tracery of the lines on a camp shell, and see how oddly and awkwardly its tents are pitched. it is not indeed always so: there is occasionally, as in the eye of the peacock's plume, an apparent precision, but still a precision far inferior to that of the drawing of the filaments which bear that lovely stain; and in the plurality of cases a degree of looseness and variation, and, still more singularly, of harshness and violence in arrangement, is admitted in color which would be monstrous in form. observe the difference in the precision of a fish's scales and of the spots on them.

xxxviii. now, why it should be that color is best seen under these circumstances i will not here endeavor to determine; nor whether the lesson we are to learn from it be that it is god's will that all manner of delights should never be combined in one thing. but the fact is certain, that color is always by him arranged in these simple or rude forms, and as certain that, therefore, it must be best seen in them, and that we shall never mend by refining its arrangements. experience teaches us the same thing. infinite nonsense has been written about the union of perfect color with perfect form. they never will, never can be united. color, to be perfect, must have a soft outline or a simple one: it cannot have a refined one; and you will never produce a good painted window with good figure-drawing in it. you will lose perfection of color as you give perfection of line. try to put in order and form the colors of a piece of opal.

xxxix. i conclude, then, that all arrangements of color, for its own sake, in graceful forms, are barbarous; and that, to paint a color pattern with the lovely lines of a greek leaf moulding, is an utterly savage procedure. i cannot find anything in natural color like this: it is not in the bond. i find[pg 135] it in all natural form—never in natural color. if, then, our architectural color is to be beautiful as its form was, by being imitative, we are limited to these conditions—to simple masses of it, to zones, as in the rainbow and the zebra; cloudings and flamings, as in marble shells and plumage, or spots of various shapes and dimensions. all these conditions are susceptible of various degrees of sharpness and delicacy, and of complication in arrangement. the zone may become a delicate line, and arrange itself in chequers and zig-zags. the flaming may be more or less defined, as on a tulip leaf, and may at last be represented by a triangle of color, and arrange itself in stars or other shapes; the spot may be also graduated into a stain, or defined into a square or circle. the most exquisite harmonies may be composed of these simple elements: some soft and full of flushed and melting spaces of color; others piquant and sparkling, or deep and rich, formed of close groups of the fiery fragments: perfect and lovely proportion may be exhibited in the relation of their quantities, infinite invention in their disposition: but, in all cases, their shape will be effective only as it determines their quantity, and regulates their operation on each other; points or edges of one being introduced between breadths of others, and so on. triangular and barred forms are therefore convenient, or others the simplest possible; leaving the pleasure of the spectator to be taken in the color, and in that only. curved outlines, especially if refined, deaden the color, and confuse the mind. even in figure painting the greatest colorists have either melted their outline away, as often correggio and rubens; or purposely made their masses of ungainly shape, as titian; or placed their brightest hues in costume, where they could get quaint patterns, as veronese, and especially angelico, with whom, however, the absolute virtue of color is secondary to grace of line. hence, he never uses the blended hues of correggio, like those on the wing of the little cupid, in the "venus and mercury," but always the severest type—the peacock plume. any of these men would have looked with infinite disgust upon the leafage and scrollwork which form the ground of color in our modern painted[pg 136] windows, and yet all whom i have named were much infected with the love of renaissance designs. we must also allow for the freedom of the painter's subject, and looseness of his associated lines; a pattern being severe in a picture, which is over luxurious upon a building. i believe, therefore, that it is impossible to be over quaint or angular in architectural coloring; and thus many dispositions which i have had occasion to reprobate in form, are, in color, the best that can be invented. i have always, for instance, spoken with contempt of the tudor style, for this reason, that, having surrendered all pretence to spaciousness and breadth,—having divided its surfaces by an infinite number of lines, it yet sacrifices the only characters which can make lines beautiful; sacrifices all the variety and grace which long atoned for the caprice of the flamboyant, and adopts, for its leading feature, an entanglement of cross bars and verticals, showing about as much invention or skill of design as the reticulation of the bricklayer's sieve. yet this very reticulation would in color be highly beautiful; and all the heraldry, and other features which, in form, are monstrous, may be delightful as themes of color (so long as there are no fluttering or over-twisted lines in them); and this observe, because, when colored, they take the place of a mere pattern, and the resemblance to nature, which could not be found in their sculptured forms, is found in their piquant variegation of other surfaces. there is a beautiful and bright bit of wall painting behind the duomo of verona, composed of coats of arms, whose bearings are balls of gold set in bars of green (altered blue?) and white, with cardinal's hats in alternate squares. this is of course, however, fit only for domestic work. the front of the doge's palace at venice is the purest and most chaste model that i can name (but one) of the fit application of color to public buildings. the sculpture and mouldings are all white; but the wall surface is chequered with marble blocks of pale rose, the chequers being in no wise harmonized, or fitted to the forms of the windows; but looking as if the surface had been completed first, and the windows cut out of it. in plate xii. fig. 2 the reader will see two of the patterns[pg 137] used in green and white, on the columns of san michele of lucca, every column having a different design. both are beautiful, but the upper one certainly the best. yet in sculpture its lines would have been perfectly barbarous, and those even of the lower not enough refined.

xl. restraining ourselves, therefore, to the use of such simple patterns, so far forth as our color is subordinate either to architectural structure, or sculptural form, we have yet one more manner of ornamentation to add to our general means of effect, monochrome design, the intermediate condition between coloring and carving. the relations of the entire system of architectural decoration may then be thus expressed.

1. organic form dominant. true, independent sculpture, and alto-relievo; rich capitals, and mouldings; to be elaborate in completion of form, not abstract, and either to be left in pure white marble, or most cautiously touched with color in points and borders only, in a system not concurrent with their forms.

2. organic form sub-dominant. basso-relievo or intaglio. to be more abstract in proportion to the reduction of depth; to be also more rigid and simple in contour; to be touched with color more boldly and in an increased degree, exactly in proportion to the reduced depth and fulness of form, but still in a system non-concurrent with their forms.

3. organic form abstracted to outline. monochrome design, still farther reduced to simplicity of contour, and therefore admitting for the first time the color to be concurrent with its outlines; that is to say, as its name imports, the entire figure to be detached in one color from a ground of another.

4. organic forms entirely lost. geometrical patterns or variable cloudings in the most vivid color.

on the opposite side of this scale, ascending from the color pattern, i would place the various forms of painting which may be associated with architecture: primarily, and as most[pg 138] fit for such purpose, the mosaic, highly abstract in treatment, and introducing brilliant color in masses; the madonna of torcello being, as i think, the noblest type of the manner, and the baptistery of parma the richest: next, the purely decorative fresco, like that of the arena chapel; finally, the fresco becoming principal, as in the vatican and sistine. but i cannot, with any safety, follow the principles of abstraction in this pictorial ornament; since the noblest examples of it appear to me to owe their architectural applicability to their archaic manner; and i think that the abstraction and admirable simplicity which render them fit media of the most splendid coloring, cannot be recovered by a voluntary condescension. the byzantines themselves would not, i think, if they could have drawn the figure better, have used it for a color decoration; and that use, as peculiar to a condition of childhood, however noble and full of promise, cannot be included among those modes of adornment which are now legitimate or even possible. there is a difficulty in the management of the painted window for the same reason, which has not yet been met, and we must conquer that first, before we can venture to consider the wall as a painted window on a large scale. pictorial subject, without such abstraction, becomes necessarily principal, or, at all events, ceases to be the architect's concern; its plan must be left to the painter after the completion of the building, as in the works of veronese and giorgione on the palaces of venice.

xli. pure architectural decoration, then, may be considered as limited to the four kinds above specified; of which each glides almost imperceptibly into the other. thus, the elgin frieze is a monochrome in a state of transition to sculpture, retaining, as i think, the half-cast skin too long. of pure monochrome, i have given an example in plate vi., from the noble front of st. michele of lucca. it contains forty such arches, all covered with equally elaborate ornaments, entirely drawn by cutting out their ground to about the depth of an inch in the flat white marble, and filling the spaces with pieces of green serpentine; a most elaborate mode of sculpture, requiring excessive care and precision in the fitting of[pg 139] the edges, and of course double work, the same line needing to be cut both in the marble and serpentine. the excessive simplicity of the forms will be at once perceived; the eyes of the figures of animals, for instance, being indicated only by a round dot, formed by a little inlet circle of serpentine, about half an inch over: but, though simple, they admit often much grace of curvature, as in the neck of the bird seen above the right hand pillar.14 the pieces of serpentine have fallen out in many places, giving the black shadows, as seen under the horseman's arm and bird's neck, and in the semi-circular line round the arch, once filled with some pattern. it would have illustrated my point better to have restored the lost portions, but i always draw a thing exactly as it is, hating restoration of any kind; and i would especially direct the reader's attention to the completion of the forms in the sculptured ornament of the marble cornices, as opposed to the abstraction of the monochrome figures, of the ball and cross patterns between the arches, and of the triangular ornament round the arch on the left.

xlii. i have an intense love for these monochrome figures, owing to their wonderful life and spirit in all the works on which i found them; nevertheless, i believe that the excessive degree of abstraction which they imply necessitates our placing them in the rank of a progressive or imperfect art, and that a perfect building should rather be composed of the highest sculpture (organic form dominant and sub-dominant), associated with pattern colors on the flat or broad surfaces. and we find, in fact, that the cathedral of pisa, which is a higher type than that of lucca, exactly follows this condition, the color being put in geometrical patterns on its surfaces, and animal-forms and lovely leafage used in the sculptured cornices and pillars. and i think that the grace of the carved forms is best seen when it is thus boldly opposed to severe traceries of color, while the color itself is, as we have seen, always most piquant when it is put into sharp angular arrangements. thus the sculpture is approved and set off by the color, and the color seen to the best advantage in its opposition both to the whiteness and the grace of the carved marble.[pg 140]

xliii. in the course of this and the preceding chapters, i have now separately enumerated most of the conditions of power and beauty, which in the outset i stated to be the grounds of the deepest impressions with which architecture could affect the human mind; but i would ask permission to recapitulate them in order to see if there be any building which i may offer as an example of the unison, in such manner as is possible, of them all. glancing back, then, to the beginning of the third chapter, and introducing in their place the conditions incidentally determined in the two previous sections, we shall have the following list of noble characters:

considerable size, exhibited by simple terminal lines (chap. iii. § 6). projection towards the top (§ 7). breadth of flat surface (§ 8). square compartments of that surface (§ 9). varied and visible masonry (§ 11). vigorous depth of shadow (§ 13), exhibited especially by pierced traceries (§ 18). varied proportion in ascent (chap. iv. § 28). lateral symmetry (§ 28). sculpture most delicate at the base (chap. i. § 12). enriched quantity of ornament at the top (§ 13). sculpture abstract in inferior ornaments and mouldings (chap. iv. § 31), complete in animal forms (§ 33). both to be executed in white marble (§ 40). vivid color introduced in flat geometrical patterns (§ 39), and obtained by the use of naturally colored stone (§ 35).

these characteristics occur more or less in different buildings, some in one and some in another. but all together, and all in their highest possible relative degrees, they exist, as far as i know, only in one building in the world, the campanile of giotto at florence. the drawing of the tracery of its upper story, which heads this chapter, rude as it is, will nevertheless give the reader some better conception of that tower's magnificence than the thin outlines in which it is usually portrayed. in its first appeal to the stranger's eye there is something unpleasing; a mingling, as it seems to him, of over severity with over minuteness. but let him give it time, as he should to all other consummate art. i remember well how, when a boy, i used to despise that campanile, and think it meanly smooth and finished. but i have since lived beside it many a day, and looked out upon it from my windows by sunlight and[pg 141] moonlight, and i shall not soon forget how profound and gloomy appeared to me the savageness of the northern gothic, when i afterwards stood, for the first time, beneath the front of salisbury. the contrast is indeed strange, if it could be quickly felt, between the rising of those grey walls out of their quiet swarded space, like dark and barren rocks out of a green lake, with their rude, mouldering, rough-grained shafts, and triple lights, without tracery or other ornament than the martins' nests in the height of them, and that bright, smooth, sunny surface of glowing jasper, those spiral shafts and fairy traceries, so white, so faint, so crystalline, that their slight shapes are hardly traced in darkness on the pallor of the eastern sky, that serene height of mountain alabaster, colored like a morning cloud, and chased like a sea shell. and if this be, as i believe it, the model and mirror of perfect architecture, is there not something to be learned by looking back to the early life of him who raised it? i said that the power of human mind had its growth in the wilderness; much more must the love and the conception of that beauty, whose every line and hue we have seen to be, at the best, a faded image of god's daily work, and an arrested ray of some star of creation, be given chiefly in the places which he has gladdened by planting there the fir tree and the pine. not within the walls of florence, but among the far away fields of her lilies, was the child trained who was to raise that headstone of beauty above the towers of watch and war. remember all that he became; count the sacred thoughts with which he filled the heart of italy; ask those who followed him what they learned at his feet; and when you have numbered his labors, and received their testimony, if it seem to you that god had verily poured out upon this his servant no common nor restrained portion of his spirit, and that he was indeed a king among the children of men, remember also that the legend upon his crown was that of david's:—"i took thee from the sheepcote, and from following the sheep."

先看到这(加入书签) | 推荐本书 | 打开书架 | 返回首页 | 返回书页 | 错误报告 | 返回顶部
热门推荐