天下书楼
会员中心 我的书架
当前位置:天下书楼 > Meno

INTRODUCTION.

(快捷键←)[没有了]  [回目录]  [下一章](快捷键→)

this dialogue begins abruptly with a question of meno, who asks, 'whether virtue can be taught.' socrates replies that he does not as yet know what virtue is, and has never known anyone who did. 'then he cannot have met gorgias when he was at athens.' yes, socrates had met him, but he has a bad memory, and has forgotten what gorgias said. will meno tell him his own notion, which is probably not very different from that of gorgias? 'o yes—nothing easier: there is the virtue of a man, of a woman, of an old man, and of a child; there is a virtue of every age and state of life, all of which may be easily described.'

socrates reminds meno that this is only an enumeration of the virtues and not a definition of the notion which is common to them all. in a second attempt meno defines virtue to be 'the power of command.' but to this, again, exceptions are taken. for there must be a virtue of those who obey, as well as of those who command; and the power of command must be justly or not unjustly exercised. meno is very ready to admit that justice is virtue: 'would you say virtue or a virtue, for there are other virtues, such as courage, temperance, and the like; just as round is a figure, and black and white are colours, and yet there are other figures and other colours. let meno take the examples of figure and colour, and try to define them.' meno confesses his inability, and after a process of interrogation, in which socrates explains to him the nature of a 'simile in multis,' socrates himself defines figure as 'the accompaniment of colour.' but some one may object that he does not know the meaning of the word 'colour;' and if he is a candid friend, and not a mere disputant, socrates is willing to furnish him with a simpler and more philosophical definition, into which no disputed word is allowed to intrude: 'figure is the limit of form.' meno imperiously insists that he must still have a definition of colour. some raillery follows; and at length socrates is induced to reply, 'that colour is the effluence of form, sensible, and in due proportion to the sight.' this definition is exactly suited to the taste of meno, who welcomes the familiar language of gorgias and empedocles. socrates is of opinion that the more abstract or dialectical definition of figure is far better.

now that meno has been made to understand the nature of a general definition, he answers in the spirit of a greek gentleman, and in the words of a poet, 'that virtue is to delight in things honourable, and to have the power of getting them.' this is a nearer approximation than he has yet made to a complete definition, and, regarded as a piece of proverbial or popular morality, is not far from the truth. but the objection is urged, 'that the honourable is the good,' and as every one equally desires the good, the point of the definition is contained in the words, 'the power of getting them.' 'and they must be got justly or with justice.' the definition will then stand thus: 'virtue is the power of getting good with justice.' but justice is a part of virtue, and therefore virtue is the getting of good with a part of virtue. the definition repeats the word defined.

meno complains that the conversation of socrates has the effect of a torpedo's shock upon him. when he talks with other persons he has plenty to say about virtue; in the presence of socrates, his thoughts desert him. socrates replies that he is only the cause of perplexity in others, because he is himself perplexed. he proposes to continue the enquiry. but how, asks meno, can he enquire either into what he knows or into what he does not know? this is a sophistical puzzle, which, as socrates remarks, saves a great deal of trouble to him who accepts it. but the puzzle has a real difficulty latent under it, to which socrates will endeavour to find a reply. the difficulty is the origin of knowledge:—

he has heard from priests and priestesses, and from the poet pindar, of an immortal soul which is born again and again in successive periods of existence, returning into this world when she has paid the penalty of ancient crime, and, having wandered over all places of the upper and under world, and seen and known all things at one time or other, is by association out of one thing capable of recovering all. for nature is of one kindred; and every soul has a seed or germ which may be developed into all knowledge. the existence of this latent knowledge is further proved by the interrogation of one of meno's slaves, who, in the skilful hands of socrates, is made to acknowledge some elementary relations of geometrical figures. the theorem that the square of the diagonal is double the square of the side—that famous discovery of primitive mathematics, in honour of which the legendary pythagoras is said to have sacrificed a hecatomb—is elicited from him. the first step in the process of teaching has made him conscious of his own ignorance. he has had the 'torpedo's shock' given him, and is the better for the operation. but whence had the uneducated man this knowledge? he had never learnt geometry in this world; nor was it born with him; he must therefore have had it when he was not a man. and as he always either was or was not a man, he must have always had it. (compare phaedo.)

after socrates has given this specimen of the true nature of teaching, the original question of the teachableness of virtue is renewed. again he professes a desire to know 'what virtue is' first. but he is willing to argue the question, as mathematicians say, under an hypothesis. he will assume that if virtue is knowledge, then virtue can be taught. (this was the stage of the argument at which the protagoras concluded.)

socrates has no difficulty in showing that virtue is a good, and that goods, whether of body or mind, must be under the direction of knowledge. upon the assumption just made, then, virtue is teachable. but where are the teachers? there are none to be found. this is extremely discouraging. virtue is no sooner discovered to be teachable, than the discovery follows that it is not taught. virtue, therefore, is and is not teachable.

in this dilemma an appeal is made to anytus, a respectable and well-to-do citizen of the old school, and a family friend of meno, who happens to be present. he is asked 'whether meno shall go to the sophists and be taught.' the suggestion throws him into a rage. 'to whom, then, shall meno go?' asks socrates. to any athenian gentleman—to the great athenian statesmen of past times. socrates replies here, as elsewhere (laches, prot.), that themistocles, pericles, and other great men, had sons to whom they would surely, if they could have done so, have imparted their own political wisdom; but no one ever heard that these sons of theirs were remarkable for anything except riding and wrestling and similar accomplishments. anytus is angry at the imputation which is cast on his favourite statesmen, and on a class to which he supposes himself to belong; he breaks off with a significant hint. the mention of another opportunity of talking with him, and the suggestion that meno may do the athenian people a service by pacifying him, are evident allusions to the trial of socrates.

socrates returns to the consideration of the question 'whether virtue is teachable,' which was denied on the ground that there are no teachers of it: (for the sophists are bad teachers, and the rest of the world do not profess to teach). but there is another point which we failed to observe, and in which gorgias has never instructed meno, nor prodicus socrates. this is the nature of right opinion. for virtue may be under the guidance of right opinion as well as of knowledge; and right opinion is for practical purposes as good as knowledge, but is incapable of being taught, and is also liable, like the images of daedalus, to 'walk off,' because not bound by the tie of the cause. this is the sort of instinct which is possessed by statesmen, who are not wise or knowing persons, but only inspired or divine. the higher virtue, which is identical with knowledge, is an ideal only. if the statesman had this knowledge, and could teach what he knew, he would be like tiresias in the world below,—'he alone has wisdom, but the rest flit like shadows.'

this dialogue is an attempt to answer the question, can virtue be taught? no one would either ask or answer such a question in modern times. but in the age of socrates it was only by an effort that the mind could rise to a general notion of virtue as distinct from the particular virtues of courage, liberality, and the like. and when a hazy conception of this ideal was attained, it was only by a further effort that the question of the teachableness of virtue could be resolved.

the answer which is given by plato is paradoxical enough, and seems rather intended to stimulate than to satisfy enquiry. virtue is knowledge, and therefore virtue can be taught. but virtue is not taught, and therefore in this higher and ideal sense there is no virtue and no knowledge. the teaching of the sophists is confessedly inadequate, and meno, who is their pupil, is ignorant of the very nature of general terms. he can only produce out of their armoury the sophism, 'that you can neither enquire into what you know nor into what you do not know;' to which socrates replies by his theory of reminiscence.

to the doctrine that virtue is knowledge, plato has been constantly tending in the previous dialogues. but the new truth is no sooner found than it vanishes away. 'if there is knowledge, there must be teachers; and where are the teachers?' there is no knowledge in the higher sense of systematic, connected, reasoned knowledge, such as may one day be attained, and such as plato himself seems to see in some far off vision of a single science. and there are no teachers in the higher sense of the word; that is to say, no real teachers who will arouse the spirit of enquiry in their pupils, and not merely instruct them in rhetoric or impart to them ready-made information for a fee of 'one' or of 'fifty drachms.' plato is desirous of deepening the notion of education, and therefore he asserts the paradox that there are no educators. this paradox, though different in form, is not really different from the remark which is often made in modern times by those who would depreciate either the methods of education commonly employed, or the standard attained—that 'there is no true education among us.'

there remains still a possibility which must not be overlooked. even if there be no true knowledge, as is proved by 'the wretched state of education,' there may be right opinion, which is a sort of guessing or divination resting on no knowledge of causes, and incommunicable to others. this is the gift which our statesmen have, as is proved by the circumstance that they are unable to impart their knowledge to their sons. those who are possessed of it cannot be said to be men of science or philosophers, but they are inspired and divine.

there may be some trace of irony in this curious passage, which forms the concluding portion of the dialogue. but plato certainly does not mean to intimate that the supernatural or divine is the true basis of human life. to him knowledge, if only attainable in this world, is of all things the most divine. yet, like other philosophers, he is willing to admit that 'probability is the guide of life (butler's analogy.);' and he is at the same time desirous of contrasting the wisdom which governs the world with a higher wisdom. there are many instincts, judgments, and anticipations of the human mind which cannot be reduced to rule, and of which the grounds cannot always be given in words. a person may have some skill or latent experience which he is able to use himself and is yet unable to teach others, because he has no principles, and is incapable of collecting or arranging his ideas. he has practice, but not theory; art, but not science. this is a true fact of psychology, which is recognized by plato in this passage. but he is far from saying, as some have imagined, that inspiration or divine grace is to be regarded as higher than knowledge. he would not have preferred the poet or man of action to the philosopher, or the virtue of custom to the virtue based upon ideas.

also here, as in the ion and phaedrus, plato appears to acknowledge an unreasoning element in the higher nature of man. the philosopher only has knowledge, and yet the statesman and the poet are inspired. there may be a sort of irony in regarding in this way the gifts of genius. but there is no reason to suppose that he is deriding them, any more than he is deriding the phenomena of love or of enthusiasm in the symposium, or of oracles in the apology, or of divine intimations when he is speaking of the daemonium of socrates. he recognizes the lower form of right opinion, as well as the higher one of science, in the spirit of one who desires to include in his philosophy every aspect of human life; just as he recognizes the existence of popular opinion as a fact, and the sophists as the expression of it.

this dialogue contains the first intimation of the doctrine of reminiscence and of the immortality of the soul. the proof is very slight, even slighter than in the phaedo and republic. because men had abstract ideas in a previous state, they must have always had them, and their souls therefore must have always existed. for they must always have been either men or not men. the fallacy of the latter words is transparent. and socrates himself appears to be conscious of their weakness; for he adds immediately afterwards, 'i have said some things of which i am not altogether confident.' (compare phaedo.) it may be observed, however, that the fanciful notion of pre-existence is combined with a true but partial view of the origin and unity of knowledge, and of the association of ideas. knowledge is prior to any particular knowledge, and exists not in the previous state of the individual, but of the race. it is potential, not actual, and can only be appropriated by strenuous exertion.

the idealism of plato is here presented in a less developed form than in the phaedo and phaedrus. nothing is said of the pre-existence of ideas of justice, temperance, and the like. nor is socrates positive of anything but the duty of enquiry. the doctrine of reminiscence too is explained more in accordance with fact and experience as arising out of the affinities of nature (ate tes thuseos oles suggenous ouses). modern philosophy says that all things in nature are dependent on one another; the ancient philosopher had the same truth latent in his mind when he affirmed that out of one thing all the rest may be recovered. the subjective was converted by him into an objective; the mental phenomenon of the association of ideas (compare phaedo) became a real chain of existences. the germs of two valuable principles of education may also be gathered from the 'words of priests and priestesses:' (1) that true knowledge is a knowledge of causes (compare aristotle's theory of episteme); and (2) that the process of learning consists not in what is brought to the learner, but in what is drawn out of him.

some lesser points of the dialogue may be noted, such as (1) the acute observation that meno prefers the familiar definition, which is embellished with poetical language, to the better and truer one; or (2) the shrewd reflection, which may admit of an application to modern as well as to ancient teachers, that the sophists having made large fortunes; this must surely be a criterion of their powers of teaching, for that no man could get a living by shoemaking who was not a good shoemaker; or (3) the remark conveyed, almost in a word, that the verbal sceptic is saved the labour of thought and enquiry (ouden dei to toiouto zeteseos). characteristic also of the temper of the socratic enquiry is, (4) the proposal to discuss the teachableness of virtue under an hypothesis, after the manner of the mathematicians; and (5) the repetition of the favourite doctrine which occurs so frequently in the earlier and more socratic dialogues, and gives a colour to all of them—that mankind only desire evil through ignorance; (6) the experiment of eliciting from the slave-boy the mathematical truth which is latent in him, and (7) the remark that he is all the better for knowing his ignorance.

the character of meno, like that of critias, has no relation to the actual circumstances of his life. plato is silent about his treachery to the ten thousand greeks, which xenophon has recorded, as he is also silent about the crimes of critias. he is a thessalian alcibiades, rich and luxurious—a spoilt child of fortune, and is described as the hereditary friend of the great king. like alcibiades he is inspired with an ardent desire of knowledge, and is equally willing to learn of socrates and of the sophists. he may be regarded as standing in the same relation to gorgias as hippocrates in the protagoras to the other great sophist. he is the sophisticated youth on whom socrates tries his cross-examining powers, just as in the charmides, the lysis, and the euthydemus, ingenuous boyhood is made the subject of a similar experiment. he is treated by socrates in a half-playful manner suited to his character; at the same time he appears not quite to understand the process to which he is being subjected. for he is exhibited as ignorant of the very elements of dialectics, in which the sophists have failed to instruct their disciple. his definition of virtue as 'the power and desire of attaining things honourable,' like the first definition of justice in the republic, is taken from a poet. his answers have a sophistical ring, and at the same time show the sophistical incapacity to grasp a general notion.

anytus is the type of the narrow-minded man of the world, who is indignant at innovation, and equally detests the popular teacher and the true philosopher. he seems, like aristophanes, to regard the new opinions, whether of socrates or the sophists, as fatal to athenian greatness. he is of the same class as callicles in the gorgias, but of a different variety; the immoral and sophistical doctrines of callicles are not attributed to him. the moderation with which he is described is remarkable, if he be the accuser of socrates, as is apparently indicated by his parting words. perhaps plato may have been desirous of showing that the accusation of socrates was not to be attributed to badness or malevolence, but rather to a tendency in men's minds. or he may have been regardless of the historical truth of the characters of his dialogue, as in the case of meno and critias. like chaerephon (apol.) the real anytus was a democrat, and had joined thrasybulus in the conflict with the thirty.

the protagoras arrived at a sort of hypothetical conclusion, that if 'virtue is knowledge, it can be taught.' in the euthydemus, socrates himself offered an example of the manner in which the true teacher may draw out the mind of youth; this was in contrast to the quibbling follies of the sophists. in the meno the subject is more developed; the foundations of the enquiry are laid deeper, and the nature of knowledge is more distinctly explained. there is a progression by antagonism of two opposite aspects of philosophy. but at the moment when we approach nearest, the truth doubles upon us and passes out of our reach. we seem to find that the ideal of knowledge is irreconcilable with experience. in human life there is indeed the profession of knowledge, but right opinion is our actual guide. there is another sort of progress from the general notions of socrates, who asked simply, 'what is friendship?' 'what is temperance?' 'what is courage?' as in the lysis, charmides, laches, to the transcendentalism of plato, who, in the second stage of his philosophy, sought to find the nature of knowledge in a prior and future state of existence.

the difficulty in framing general notions which has appeared in this and in all the previous dialogues recurs in the gorgias and theaetetus as well as in the republic. in the gorgias too the statesmen reappear, but in stronger opposition to the philosopher. they are no longer allowed to have a divine insight, but, though acknowledged to have been clever men and good speakers, are denounced as 'blind leaders of the blind.' the doctrine of the immortality of the soul is also carried further, being made the foundation not only of a theory of knowledge, but of a doctrine of rewards and punishments. in the republic the relation of knowledge to virtue is described in a manner more consistent with modern distinctions. the existence of the virtues without the possession of knowledge in the higher or philosophical sense is admitted to be possible. right opinion is again introduced in the theaetetus as an account of knowledge, but is rejected on the ground that it is irrational (as here, because it is not bound by the tie of the cause), and also because the conception of false opinion is given up as hopeless. the doctrines of plato are necessarily different at different times of his life, as new distinctions are realized, or new stages of thought attained by him. we are not therefore justified, in order to take away the appearance of inconsistency, in attributing to him hidden meanings or remote allusions.

there are no external criteria by which we can determine the date of the meno. there is no reason to suppose that any of the dialogues of plato were written before the death of socrates; the meno, which appears to be one of the earliest of them, is proved to have been of a later date by the allusion of anytus.

we cannot argue that plato was more likely to have written, as he has done, of meno before than after his miserable death; for we have already seen, in the examples of charmides and critias, that the characters in plato are very far from resembling the same characters in history. the repulsive picture which is given of him in the anabasis of xenophon, where he also appears as the friend of aristippus 'and a fair youth having lovers,' has no other trait of likeness to the meno of plato.

the place of the meno in the series is doubtfully indicated by internal evidence. the main character of the dialogue is socrates; but to the 'general definitions' of socrates is added the platonic doctrine of reminiscence. the problems of virtue and knowledge have been discussed in the lysis, laches, charmides, and protagoras; the puzzle about knowing and learning has already appeared in the euthydemus. the doctrines of immortality and pre-existence are carried further in the phaedrus and phaedo; the distinction between opinion and knowledge is more fully developed in the theaetetus. the lessons of prodicus, whom he facetiously calls his master, are still running in the mind of socrates. unlike the later platonic dialogues, the meno arrives at no conclusion. hence we are led to place the dialogue at some point of time later than the protagoras, and earlier than the phaedrus and gorgias. the place which is assigned to it in this work is due mainly to the desire to bring together in a single volume all the dialogues which contain allusions to the trial and death of socrates.

先看到这(加入书签) | 推荐本书 | 打开书架 | 返回首页 | 返回书页 | 错误报告 | 返回顶部